Literature MCQ Quiz - Objective Question with Answer for Literature - Download Free PDF
Last updated on May 22, 2025
Latest Literature MCQ Objective Questions
Literature Question 1:
Comprehension:
The 17th century in Europe was a crucible of intellectual ferment, a period marked by the waning influence of scholasticism and the burgeoning dawn of the Scientific Revolution. Amidst this intellectual upheaval, where established truths were being questioned by new astronomical discoveries and philosophical skepticism, emerged René Descartes (1596-1650), a figure whose radical methodology and foundational pronouncements would irrevocably alter the course of Western philosophy. Dissatisfied with the uncertainties and contradictions inherent in the knowledge systems of his time, Descartes embarked on an ambitious intellectual quest: to establish a bedrock of indubitable truth upon which all other knowledge could be securely built. His journey, famously encapsulated by the phrase Cogito, ergo sum ("I think, therefore I am"), represents a pivotal moment in the transition from medieval to modern thought, emphasizing the power of individual reason and subjective experience as the starting point for philosophical inquiry.
Descartes's method for achieving this certainty was systematic doubt, a process he meticulously outlined in his Discourse on Method (1637) and Meditations on First Philosophy (1641). He resolved to reject as false anything about which he could conceive the slightest doubt. This radical skepticism extended to sensory experience, which he noted could be deceptive (e.g., optical illusions). He even entertained the possibility of a "malicious demon" or "evil genius" (or a powerful deceiver) who might be systematically misleading him about everything, including the most fundamental mathematical truths. This hypothetical demon was Descartes's ultimate skeptical challenge, pushing doubt to its absolute extreme. The purpose of this hyperbolic doubt was not to revel in skepticism, but to purify his beliefs, stripping away all that was uncertain to reveal what, if anything, remained unshakable.
It was in this crucible of doubt that Descartes discovered his foundational truth: the Cogito, ergo sum. Even if a malicious demon were deceiving him about everything, the very act of being deceived, or of doubting, presupposed an "I" that was doing the doubting or being deceived. One cannot doubt without existing. The act of thinking (in its broadest sense, encompassing doubting, understanding, affirming, denying, willing, imagining, and feeling) necessarily implies an existent thinker. As he famously articulated in Meditations: "I noticed that while I was trying to think of everything as false, it had to be the case that I, who was thinking this, was something. And noticing that this truth, 'I think, therefore I am,' was so firm and so certain that all the most extravagant suppositions of the sceptics were incapable of shaking it, I judged that I could accept it without scruple as the first principle of the philosophy I was seeking."
The Cogito is not merely a logical inference or a syllogism (where "I think" is a premise and "I am" is a conclusion). Rather, it is presented as an immediate, intuitive apprehension of one's own existence as a thinking thing. It is an axiomatic truth, self-evident upon reflection. What the Cogito establishes is the existence of the self as a res cogitans – a thinking substance, distinct from any physical body or external world. This distinction laid the groundwork for Cartesian dualism, the theory that mind and body are two fundamentally different kinds of substance. The mind, being a thinking, non-extended substance, is primary and knowable with certainty, while the extended, physical body and the external world are known only through the mediation of the senses, which are subject to doubt.
From this singular, indubitable truth of his own existence as a thinking being, Descartes sought to rebuild the edifice of knowledge. His next crucial step was to prove the existence of God. He argued that the idea of a perfect, infinite God could not have originated from his own finite and imperfect mind; therefore, such an idea must have been implanted by God Himself. Furthermore, he presented an ontological argument, asserting that the very concept of a supremely perfect being necessarily includes existence. Once God's existence was established as a perfect and benevolent being, Descartes could then dismiss the malicious demon hypothesis. A perfect God, being supremely good, would not deceive him. This divine guarantee then allowed Descartes to trust his clear and distinct perceptions of the external world, thus moving from the certainty of the self to the certainty of God, and finally to the certainty of the material world.
The legacy of Descartes's Cogito is immense and multifaceted. It shifted the foundation of philosophy from external authority or tradition to the internal, subjective experience of the individual. This emphasis on the thinking subject became a hallmark of modern philosophy, influencing thinkers from Locke and Berkeley to Kant and Husserl. However, the Cogito also opened up new problems. Critics questioned how the mind (a non-physical substance) could interact with the body (a physical substance), a problem known as the mind-body problem. Others challenged the certainty of his proofs for God's existence and the external world, arguing that his entire system ultimately rested on assumptions that were not as indubitable as the Cogito itself. Despite these criticisms, Descartes's relentless pursuit of certainty, his systematic method of doubt, and his groundbreaking articulation of the Cogito remain cornerstones of philosophical inquiry, forever marking him as the progenitor of modern rationalism and a pivotal figure in the history of human thought.
The passage indicates that a significant criticism leveled against Descartes's broader philosophical system, beyond the Cogito itself, concerns:
Answer (Detailed Solution Below)
Literature Question 1 Detailed Solution
The correct answer is: The reliance on assumptions, particularly regarding God's existence, that are not as self-evident as the Cogito itself, to validate further knowledge.
Key Points
- Explanation: The final paragraph of the passage discusses criticisms leveled against Descartes's system. It states: "Critics questioned how the mind (a non-physical substance) could interact with the body (a physical substance), a problem known as the mind-body problem. Others challenged the certainty of his proofs for God's existence and the external world, arguing that his entire system ultimately rested on assumptions that were not as indubitable as the Cogito itself." Option 3 directly reflects the second part of this criticism, focusing on the foundational weakness of his system's extension beyond the Cogito, particularly concerning the proofs for God's existence and the external world. This criticism targets the very method by which Descartes sought to rebuild knowledge from his first principle.
- Why the other options are incorrect:
- 1) The inherent difficulty in proving the existence of an external, material world without resorting to circular reasoning: The passage mentions "Others challenged the certainty of his proofs for God's existence and the external world." While some historical critiques of Descartes do involve circular reasoning (the "Cartesian Circle"), the passage itself does not explicitly use this term or detail the specific challenge as "circular reasoning." It focuses on the idea that the proofs rested on "assumptions that were not as indubitable as the Cogito."
- 2) The unresolved problem of how a non-physical mind can causally interact with a physical body: This is indeed a significant criticism mentioned in the passage: "Critics questioned how the mind (a non-physical substance) could interact with the body (a physical substance), a problem known as the mind-body problem." However, Option 3 captures a broader criticism about the validity of his entire system's subsequent foundations (beyond the Cogito), which is arguably more encompassing regarding the "broader philosophical system."
- 4) His failure to adequately address the implications of subjective experience for intersubjective agreement on truth: While the passage highlights Descartes's shift to "internal, subjective experience," it does not state that a criticism against his system was his failure to address "intersubjective agreement on truth."
Literature Question 2:
Comprehension:
The 17th century in Europe was a crucible of intellectual ferment, a period marked by the waning influence of scholasticism and the burgeoning dawn of the Scientific Revolution. Amidst this intellectual upheaval, where established truths were being questioned by new astronomical discoveries and philosophical skepticism, emerged René Descartes (1596-1650), a figure whose radical methodology and foundational pronouncements would irrevocably alter the course of Western philosophy. Dissatisfied with the uncertainties and contradictions inherent in the knowledge systems of his time, Descartes embarked on an ambitious intellectual quest: to establish a bedrock of indubitable truth upon which all other knowledge could be securely built. His journey, famously encapsulated by the phrase Cogito, ergo sum ("I think, therefore I am"), represents a pivotal moment in the transition from medieval to modern thought, emphasizing the power of individual reason and subjective experience as the starting point for philosophical inquiry.
Descartes's method for achieving this certainty was systematic doubt, a process he meticulously outlined in his Discourse on Method (1637) and Meditations on First Philosophy (1641). He resolved to reject as false anything about which he could conceive the slightest doubt. This radical skepticism extended to sensory experience, which he noted could be deceptive (e.g., optical illusions). He even entertained the possibility of a "malicious demon" or "evil genius" (or a powerful deceiver) who might be systematically misleading him about everything, including the most fundamental mathematical truths. This hypothetical demon was Descartes's ultimate skeptical challenge, pushing doubt to its absolute extreme. The purpose of this hyperbolic doubt was not to revel in skepticism, but to purify his beliefs, stripping away all that was uncertain to reveal what, if anything, remained unshakable.
It was in this crucible of doubt that Descartes discovered his foundational truth: the Cogito, ergo sum. Even if a malicious demon were deceiving him about everything, the very act of being deceived, or of doubting, presupposed an "I" that was doing the doubting or being deceived. One cannot doubt without existing. The act of thinking (in its broadest sense, encompassing doubting, understanding, affirming, denying, willing, imagining, and feeling) necessarily implies an existent thinker. As he famously articulated in Meditations: "I noticed that while I was trying to think of everything as false, it had to be the case that I, who was thinking this, was something. And noticing that this truth, 'I think, therefore I am,' was so firm and so certain that all the most extravagant suppositions of the sceptics were incapable of shaking it, I judged that I could accept it without scruple as the first principle of the philosophy I was seeking."
The Cogito is not merely a logical inference or a syllogism (where "I think" is a premise and "I am" is a conclusion). Rather, it is presented as an immediate, intuitive apprehension of one's own existence as a thinking thing. It is an axiomatic truth, self-evident upon reflection. What the Cogito establishes is the existence of the self as a res cogitans – a thinking substance, distinct from any physical body or external world. This distinction laid the groundwork for Cartesian dualism, the theory that mind and body are two fundamentally different kinds of substance. The mind, being a thinking, non-extended substance, is primary and knowable with certainty, while the extended, physical body and the external world are known only through the mediation of the senses, which are subject to doubt.
From this singular, indubitable truth of his own existence as a thinking being, Descartes sought to rebuild the edifice of knowledge. His next crucial step was to prove the existence of God. He argued that the idea of a perfect, infinite God could not have originated from his own finite and imperfect mind; therefore, such an idea must have been implanted by God Himself. Furthermore, he presented an ontological argument, asserting that the very concept of a supremely perfect being necessarily includes existence. Once God's existence was established as a perfect and benevolent being, Descartes could then dismiss the malicious demon hypothesis. A perfect God, being supremely good, would not deceive him. This divine guarantee then allowed Descartes to trust his clear and distinct perceptions of the external world, thus moving from the certainty of the self to the certainty of God, and finally to the certainty of the material world.
The legacy of Descartes's Cogito is immense and multifaceted. It shifted the foundation of philosophy from external authority or tradition to the internal, subjective experience of the individual. This emphasis on the thinking subject became a hallmark of modern philosophy, influencing thinkers from Locke and Berkeley to Kant and Husserl. However, the Cogito also opened up new problems. Critics questioned how the mind (a non-physical substance) could interact with the body (a physical substance), a problem known as the mind-body problem. Others challenged the certainty of his proofs for God's existence and the external world, arguing that his entire system ultimately rested on assumptions that were not as indubitable as the Cogito itself. Despite these criticisms, Descartes's relentless pursuit of certainty, his systematic method of doubt, and his groundbreaking articulation of the Cogito remain cornerstones of philosophical inquiry, forever marking him as the progenitor of modern rationalism and a pivotal figure in the history of human thought.
According to the passage, the Cogito, ergo sum functions as Descartes's foundational truth by primarily establishing:
Answer (Detailed Solution Below)
Literature Question 2 Detailed Solution
The correct answer is: The intuitive and immediate apprehension of one's own existence as a thinking substance.
Key Points
- Explanation: The passage explicitly describes the function of the Cogito in Paragraph 4: "The Cogito is not merely a logical inference or a syllogism... Rather, it is presented as an immediate, intuitive apprehension of one's own existence as a thinking thing. It is an axiomatic truth, self-evident upon reflection. What the Cogito establishes is the existence of the self as a res cogitans – a thinking substance, distinct from any physical body or external world." Option 2 directly and accurately reflects these key phrases: "intuitive and immediate apprehension" and "one's own existence as a thinking substance."
- Why the other options are incorrect:
- 1) The existence of a perfect and benevolent God who guarantees the reliability of human reason: Proving God's existence was Descartes's next crucial step (Paragraph 5) after establishing the Cogito. The Cogito itself establishes the existence of the thinking self, not God.
- 3) The logical inference that physical existence is a necessary precondition for the act of thought: This contradicts the passage. Paragraph 4 states that the Cogito establishes the self as a "thinking substance, distinct from any physical body or external world." Descartes's point was that thought itself proves existence without needing a physical body.
- 4) The inherent connection between the mind and the body, leading to Cartesian dualism: The Cogito, by establishing the self as a "thinking substance, distinct from any physical body," laid the groundwork for Cartesian dualism (the theory of mind and body as fundamentally different substances). However, it does not primarily establish an "inherent connection"; in fact, the distinction it highlights is what led to the famous "mind-body problem" regarding how they interact (Paragraph 6).
- In summary, option 2 precisely articulates what the passage states the Cogito primarily establishes as Descartes's foundational truth.
Literature Question 3:
Comprehension:
The 17th century in Europe was a crucible of intellectual ferment, a period marked by the waning influence of scholasticism and the burgeoning dawn of the Scientific Revolution. Amidst this intellectual upheaval, where established truths were being questioned by new astronomical discoveries and philosophical skepticism, emerged René Descartes (1596-1650), a figure whose radical methodology and foundational pronouncements would irrevocably alter the course of Western philosophy. Dissatisfied with the uncertainties and contradictions inherent in the knowledge systems of his time, Descartes embarked on an ambitious intellectual quest: to establish a bedrock of indubitable truth upon which all other knowledge could be securely built. His journey, famously encapsulated by the phrase Cogito, ergo sum ("I think, therefore I am"), represents a pivotal moment in the transition from medieval to modern thought, emphasizing the power of individual reason and subjective experience as the starting point for philosophical inquiry.
Descartes's method for achieving this certainty was systematic doubt, a process he meticulously outlined in his Discourse on Method (1637) and Meditations on First Philosophy (1641). He resolved to reject as false anything about which he could conceive the slightest doubt. This radical skepticism extended to sensory experience, which he noted could be deceptive (e.g., optical illusions). He even entertained the possibility of a "malicious demon" or "evil genius" (or a powerful deceiver) who might be systematically misleading him about everything, including the most fundamental mathematical truths. This hypothetical demon was Descartes's ultimate skeptical challenge, pushing doubt to its absolute extreme. The purpose of this hyperbolic doubt was not to revel in skepticism, but to purify his beliefs, stripping away all that was uncertain to reveal what, if anything, remained unshakable.
It was in this crucible of doubt that Descartes discovered his foundational truth: the Cogito, ergo sum. Even if a malicious demon were deceiving him about everything, the very act of being deceived, or of doubting, presupposed an "I" that was doing the doubting or being deceived. One cannot doubt without existing. The act of thinking (in its broadest sense, encompassing doubting, understanding, affirming, denying, willing, imagining, and feeling) necessarily implies an existent thinker. As he famously articulated in Meditations: "I noticed that while I was trying to think of everything as false, it had to be the case that I, who was thinking this, was something. And noticing that this truth, 'I think, therefore I am,' was so firm and so certain that all the most extravagant suppositions of the sceptics were incapable of shaking it, I judged that I could accept it without scruple as the first principle of the philosophy I was seeking."
The Cogito is not merely a logical inference or a syllogism (where "I think" is a premise and "I am" is a conclusion). Rather, it is presented as an immediate, intuitive apprehension of one's own existence as a thinking thing. It is an axiomatic truth, self-evident upon reflection. What the Cogito establishes is the existence of the self as a res cogitans – a thinking substance, distinct from any physical body or external world. This distinction laid the groundwork for Cartesian dualism, the theory that mind and body are two fundamentally different kinds of substance. The mind, being a thinking, non-extended substance, is primary and knowable with certainty, while the extended, physical body and the external world are known only through the mediation of the senses, which are subject to doubt.
From this singular, indubitable truth of his own existence as a thinking being, Descartes sought to rebuild the edifice of knowledge. His next crucial step was to prove the existence of God. He argued that the idea of a perfect, infinite God could not have originated from his own finite and imperfect mind; therefore, such an idea must have been implanted by God Himself. Furthermore, he presented an ontological argument, asserting that the very concept of a supremely perfect being necessarily includes existence. Once God's existence was established as a perfect and benevolent being, Descartes could then dismiss the malicious demon hypothesis. A perfect God, being supremely good, would not deceive him. This divine guarantee then allowed Descartes to trust his clear and distinct perceptions of the external world, thus moving from the certainty of the self to the certainty of God, and finally to the certainty of the material world.
The legacy of Descartes's Cogito is immense and multifaceted. It shifted the foundation of philosophy from external authority or tradition to the internal, subjective experience of the individual. This emphasis on the thinking subject became a hallmark of modern philosophy, influencing thinkers from Locke and Berkeley to Kant and Husserl. However, the Cogito also opened up new problems. Critics questioned how the mind (a non-physical substance) could interact with the body (a physical substance), a problem known as the mind-body problem. Others challenged the certainty of his proofs for God's existence and the external world, arguing that his entire system ultimately rested on assumptions that were not as indubitable as the Cogito itself. Despite these criticisms, Descartes's relentless pursuit of certainty, his systematic method of doubt, and his groundbreaking articulation of the Cogito remain cornerstones of philosophical inquiry, forever marking him as the progenitor of modern rationalism and a pivotal figure in the history of human thought.
Descartes's hypothetical "malicious demon" or "evil genius" serves primarily as a tool to:
Answer (Detailed Solution Below)
Literature Question 3 Detailed Solution
The correct answer is: Push the boundaries of skepticism to its absolute extreme, thereby isolating any truth that remains undeniably certain.
Key Points
- Explanation: The passage explicitly states the purpose of the malicious demon hypothesis in Paragraph 2: "This hypothetical demon was Descartes's ultimate skeptical challenge, pushing doubt to its absolute extreme. The purpose of this hyperbolic doubt was not to revel in skepticism, but to purify his beliefs, stripping away all that was uncertain to reveal what, if anything, remained unshakable." Option 3 directly captures these key phrases: "Push the boundaries of skepticism to its absolute extreme" and "isolating any truth that remains undeniably certain" (which aligns with "reveal what, if anything, remained unshakable").
- Why the other options are incorrect:
- Argue for the inherent unreliability of all sensory experiences and mathematical truths: The demon is a tool to test the reliability of these, not an argument for their inherent unreliability as a final conclusion. Descartes uses it to find something beyond that unreliability.
- Illustrate the theological concept of a deceptive deity to which humans are perpetually subjected: The demon is presented as a hypothetical philosophical device, a "thought experiment," not a theological claim or an illustration of a real-world theological concept that humans are perpetually subjected to.
- Establish the logical impossibility of knowing anything beyond one's own immediate thoughts: Descartes's ultimate goal was to overcome this radical doubt and rebuild knowledge, not to establish the impossibility of knowing anything else. The demon presents the extreme challenge from which the Cogito emerges as a certainty, allowing for further knowledge (of God and the external world) to be established.
- In summary, option 3 best describes the primary function of Descartes's malicious demon, as explained in the passage.
Literature Question 4:
Comprehension:
The 17th century in Europe was a crucible of intellectual ferment, a period marked by the waning influence of scholasticism and the burgeoning dawn of the Scientific Revolution. Amidst this intellectual upheaval, where established truths were being questioned by new astronomical discoveries and philosophical skepticism, emerged René Descartes (1596-1650), a figure whose radical methodology and foundational pronouncements would irrevocably alter the course of Western philosophy. Dissatisfied with the uncertainties and contradictions inherent in the knowledge systems of his time, Descartes embarked on an ambitious intellectual quest: to establish a bedrock of indubitable truth upon which all other knowledge could be securely built. His journey, famously encapsulated by the phrase Cogito, ergo sum ("I think, therefore I am"), represents a pivotal moment in the transition from medieval to modern thought, emphasizing the power of individual reason and subjective experience as the starting point for philosophical inquiry.
Descartes's method for achieving this certainty was systematic doubt, a process he meticulously outlined in his Discourse on Method (1637) and Meditations on First Philosophy (1641). He resolved to reject as false anything about which he could conceive the slightest doubt. This radical skepticism extended to sensory experience, which he noted could be deceptive (e.g., optical illusions). He even entertained the possibility of a "malicious demon" or "evil genius" (or a powerful deceiver) who might be systematically misleading him about everything, including the most fundamental mathematical truths. This hypothetical demon was Descartes's ultimate skeptical challenge, pushing doubt to its absolute extreme. The purpose of this hyperbolic doubt was not to revel in skepticism, but to purify his beliefs, stripping away all that was uncertain to reveal what, if anything, remained unshakable.
It was in this crucible of doubt that Descartes discovered his foundational truth: the Cogito, ergo sum. Even if a malicious demon were deceiving him about everything, the very act of being deceived, or of doubting, presupposed an "I" that was doing the doubting or being deceived. One cannot doubt without existing. The act of thinking (in its broadest sense, encompassing doubting, understanding, affirming, denying, willing, imagining, and feeling) necessarily implies an existent thinker. As he famously articulated in Meditations: "I noticed that while I was trying to think of everything as false, it had to be the case that I, who was thinking this, was something. And noticing that this truth, 'I think, therefore I am,' was so firm and so certain that all the most extravagant suppositions of the sceptics were incapable of shaking it, I judged that I could accept it without scruple as the first principle of the philosophy I was seeking."
The Cogito is not merely a logical inference or a syllogism (where "I think" is a premise and "I am" is a conclusion). Rather, it is presented as an immediate, intuitive apprehension of one's own existence as a thinking thing. It is an axiomatic truth, self-evident upon reflection. What the Cogito establishes is the existence of the self as a res cogitans – a thinking substance, distinct from any physical body or external world. This distinction laid the groundwork for Cartesian dualism, the theory that mind and body are two fundamentally different kinds of substance. The mind, being a thinking, non-extended substance, is primary and knowable with certainty, while the extended, physical body and the external world are known only through the mediation of the senses, which are subject to doubt.
From this singular, indubitable truth of his own existence as a thinking being, Descartes sought to rebuild the edifice of knowledge. His next crucial step was to prove the existence of God. He argued that the idea of a perfect, infinite God could not have originated from his own finite and imperfect mind; therefore, such an idea must have been implanted by God Himself. Furthermore, he presented an ontological argument, asserting that the very concept of a supremely perfect being necessarily includes existence. Once God's existence was established as a perfect and benevolent being, Descartes could then dismiss the malicious demon hypothesis. A perfect God, being supremely good, would not deceive him. This divine guarantee then allowed Descartes to trust his clear and distinct perceptions of the external world, thus moving from the certainty of the self to the certainty of God, and finally to the certainty of the material world.
The legacy of Descartes's Cogito is immense and multifaceted. It shifted the foundation of philosophy from external authority or tradition to the internal, subjective experience of the individual. This emphasis on the thinking subject became a hallmark of modern philosophy, influencing thinkers from Locke and Berkeley to Kant and Husserl. However, the Cogito also opened up new problems. Critics questioned how the mind (a non-physical substance) could interact with the body (a physical substance), a problem known as the mind-body problem. Others challenged the certainty of his proofs for God's existence and the external world, arguing that his entire system ultimately rested on assumptions that were not as indubitable as the Cogito itself. Despite these criticisms, Descartes's relentless pursuit of certainty, his systematic method of doubt, and his groundbreaking articulation of the Cogito remain cornerstones of philosophical inquiry, forever marking him as the progenitor of modern rationalism and a pivotal figure in the history of human thought.
Which of the following best captures the central argument or primary objective of the passage?
Answer (Detailed Solution Below)
Literature Question 4 Detailed Solution
The correct answer is: To analyze Descartes's revolutionary method of systematic doubt and the Cogito, ergo sum as a foundational shift in Western philosophy.
Key Points
- Explanation:
- The passage dedicates significant attention to explaining Descartes's "systematic doubt" (Paragraph 2), the process through which he arrived at his foundational truth.
- It then thoroughly details the discovery and nature of the "Cogito, ergo sum" (Paragraphs 3 and 4), emphasizing its self-evidence and what it established (the thinking self).
- Crucially, the introductory and concluding paragraphs highlight the profound impact of this method and discovery, describing it as a "radical methodology," a "pivotal moment in the transition from medieval to modern thought," and a shift that "irrevocably alter[ed] the course of Western philosophy," emphasizing his role as the "progenitor of modern rationalism" (Paragraphs 1 and 6).
- This option perfectly encapsulates the passage's central focus on analyzing both Descartes's method and the significance of the Cogito as a transformative philosophical development.
- Why the other options are incorrect:
- To demonstrate how Descartes's philosophical system successfully resolved all major epistemological challenges of the 17th century: The passage acknowledges that "the Cogito also opened up new problems" such as the mind-body problem and that critics challenged his proofs for God's existence and the external world (Paragraph 6). Thus, it does not claim complete resolution of all challenges.
- To critique Descartes's reliance on theological arguments to establish the certainty of the external world: While the passage describes Descartes's use of theological arguments (Paragraph 5) and mentions that critics questioned their certainty (Paragraph 6), the primary purpose of the entire passage is not to critique this reliance but to explain it as part of his broader system and its impact.
- To compare Descartes's rationalism with the empiricist philosophies that emerged in the wake of his work: The passage identifies Descartes as the "progenitor of modern rationalism" and notes his influence on figures like Locke and Berkeley (who were empiricists). However, it does not engage in a detailed comparison or contrast between rationalist and empiricist philosophies; its focus remains squarely on Descartes's own work.
- In summary, option 2 best captures the analytical and explanatory objective of the passage, focusing on Descartes's revolutionary approach and its foundational impact on Western thought.
Literature Question 5:
Five jumbled up sentences, related to a topic, are given below. Four of them can be put together to form a coherent paragraph. Identify the odd one out and key in the number of the sentence as your answer.
1. Following the initial revelations, numerous women, including prominent actresses and former employees, publicly shared their accounts of alleged sexual harassment and assault by Harvey Weinstein over many years.
2. The controversy surrounding powerful Hollywood producer Harvey Weinstein, beginning with investigative reports in 2017, exposed a pattern of alleged misconduct that shocked the entertainment industry.
3. Weinstein's production company was renowned for backing critically acclaimed and commercially successful independent films that garnered numerous awards.
4. This collective outpouring of testimony, amplified by social movements, helped dismantle a long-standing culture of silence and fear that had allegedly protected abusers in Hollywood.
5. The scandal became a major catalyst for broader societal conversations about power dynamics, sexual harassment, and accountability across many industries, significantly impacting workplace norms.
Answer (Detailed Solution Below)
Literature Question 5 Detailed Solution
The correct answer is Option 3.
Key Points
- The given sentences revolve around the controversy surrounding Harvey Weinstein and its broader societal impact, particularly on issues like sexual harassment, accountability, and the #MeToo movement.
- Sentences 1, 2, 4, and 5 form a coherent narrative about the allegations, societal reactions, and cultural shifts brought about by the scandal.
- Sentence 3, however, discusses Weinstein's production company and its achievements in the film industry, which is unrelated to the main theme of the paragraph.
- Hence, Sentence 3 is the odd one out as it does not contribute to the central idea of the paragraph.
Therefore, the correct answer is Option 3.
Additional Information
- The Harvey Weinstein scandal was a pivotal moment in the global #MeToo movement, highlighting the prevalence of sexual misconduct across industries.
- The allegations against Weinstein and the public outcry led to significant cultural and legal changes, including greater awareness of workplace harassment and accountability.
- The movement encouraged survivors of abuse to come forward and share their experiences, leading to changes in workplace policies worldwide.
Top Literature MCQ Objective Questions
Directions: Select the antonym of the underlined word given in the sentence.
Lakshmibai is the most famous Indian woman to have defied the British
Answer (Detailed Solution Below)
Literature Question 6 Detailed Solution
Download Solution PDFThe correct answer is 'Accepted'
Key Points
- Let's see the meanings of the given words-
- Defied- to refuse to obey a person, decision, law, situation, etc
- Example- It is rare to see children openly defying their teachers.
- Opposed- completely different
- Example- His view of the situation is diametrically (= very strongly) opposed to mine.
- Accepted- to agree to take something
- Example- Do you accept credit cards?
- Considered- to spend time thinking about a possibility or making a decision
- Example- Don't make any decisions before you've considered the situation.
- Joined- to connect or fasten things together
- Example- A long suspension bridge joins the two islands.
- Defied- to refuse to obey a person, decision, law, situation, etc
Hence, according to the given meanings, the correct antonym is 'Accepted' i.e. Option 2.
Which of the following is a short story collection by Oscar Wilde?
Answer (Detailed Solution Below)
Literature Question 7 Detailed Solution
Download Solution PDFThe correct answer is 'The Happy Prince'.
Key Points
- Oscar Wilde was an Irish writer known as the proponent of the Aesthetic movement.
- The short stories collection 'The Happy Prince' was published in May 1888.
- The collection consists of five stories in total - "The Happy Prince", "The Nightingale and the Rose", "The Selfish Giant", "The Devoted Friend", and "The Remarkable Rocket".
Therefore, Option 1 is the correct answer.
Match the column
1. Imagery |
(a) exaggeration of a sentence |
2. Euphemism |
(b) a word or a phrase creates an image of an object |
3. Hyperbole |
(c) praise of a person or his qualities |
4. Eulogy |
(d)word or a phrase with less intense or less offence in meaning |
Answer (Detailed Solution Below)
Literature Question 8 Detailed Solution
Download Solution PDFFigure of speech: It is a word or a phrase that has some other meaning apart from its literal definitions. Below mentioned are some figure of speech:
- Imagery: When a word or a phrase creates an image of an object, it is called imagery. For example, rotten eggs refer to smell.
- Euphemism: It is the replacement of a word or a phrase with less intense or less offence in meaning. For example, ‘He died’ can also be written as ‘He passed away.
- Hyperbole: Also known as overstatement, it refers to exaggeration of a sentence. For example, ‘He wants pin-drop silence in his class’ (complete silence)
- Eulogy: It is high praise of a person or his qualities, a tribute for someone.
"The reddest flower would look as pale as snow for, all day, we drag our burden tiring".
Mention the figure of speech employed in the above lines.
Answer (Detailed Solution Below)
Literature Question 9 Detailed Solution
Download Solution PDFThe correct answer is 'Simile'.
Key Points
- The figure of speech employed in the above lines is 'Simile'.
- Simile: (the use of) an expression comparing one thing with another, always including the words "as" or "like".
- In the given sentence the flower is being compared with snow.
- Therefore, as per the points mentioned above, we find that the correct answer is Option 2.
Correct Answer: Simile.
Additional Information
- Let's look at the meaning of other words given in the Options:
- Metaphor: an expression, often found in literature, that describes a person or object by referring to something that is considered to have similar characteristics to that person or object.
- Oxymoron: a phrase that combines two words that seem to be the opposite of each other, such as a deafening silence
- Personification: the attribution of a personal nature or human characteristics to something non-human, or the representation of an abstract quality in human form
Which of the following works is not written by William Wordsworth?
Answer (Detailed Solution Below)
Literature Question 10 Detailed Solution
Download Solution PDFThe correct answer is Beyond.
Key Points
- 'Beyond' is a poem by Ella Wheeler Wilcox.
- The poem shows how short life really is and how the reader should cherish every moment of it.
- The poetess writes about how she does not fear death any more, and finds heaven right around herself among her friends and loved ones.
Important Points
- Ella is an American author and poet, whose autobiography The Worlds and I was published a year before her death.
- She is famous as the creator of the saying, "Laugh and the world laughs with you, weep and you weep alone."
Additional Information
- The Thorn was written by Wordsworth in 1789, long before he was known as the progenitor of the Romantic movement through his poems in Lyrical Ballads. It is a melodramatic poem about a woman named Martha Ray, who has lost her baby and is thus quite sad.
- The Idiot Boy was one of the most prominent inclusions in Lyrical Ballads. It is 463 lines long, and was written in five line stanzas.
- The full name of the poem is Simon Lee: The Old Huntsman, where Wordsworth expounds upon the vagaries of age, by describing the past and the the present of Simon Lee, a hunter.
Hint
- The Idiot Boy and Simon Lee are quite well-known. You can eliminate those choices first.
Choose the correct figure of speech in the following sentence:
'The wind lies asleep in the arms of dawn.'
Answer (Detailed Solution Below)
Literature Question 11 Detailed Solution
Download Solution PDFThe correct answer is 'Personification'.
Key Points
- A figure of speech is a word or phrase that possesses a separate meaning from its literal definition.
- 'Personification' has been used in line 'The wind lies asleep in the arms of dawn'.
- 'Personification' gives human qualities to non living things or ideas. 'Personification' is used to endow human qualities into inanimate objects.
- For example:
- The thunder grumbled.
- According to the above explanation 'Personification' is a figure of speech that has been used in lines 'The wind lies asleep in the arms of dawn'.
- The quality 'asleep' has been used for wind.
- Thus, option 3 will be the correct answer.
Additional Information Let's look at the meanings and examples of other given options:
- Metaphor: it makes a comparison between two unlike things or ideas.
- For example:
- Heart of stone.
- Hyperbole: it uses exaggeration for emphasis or effect.
- For example:
- I could do this forever.
- Oxymoron: an oxymoron is two contradictory terms used together.
- For example:
- Peace force.
Choose the correct tense.
By the next month, we shall _____ the project.
Answer (Detailed Solution Below)
Literature Question 12 Detailed Solution
Download Solution PDFThe correct answer is option 4, "have completed".
Key Points
- The tense used in this sentence is the future perfect tense. Future perfect tense depicts a situation where the task shall have been completed at a particular point in time in the future.
- The complete sentence is: by the next month we shall have completed the project.
- The Future Perfect Tense is used a) to indicate that an action will have been completed at some point in the future.
- The structure of the sentence is: will/shall + have/has + past participle of the verb.
So the correct option is "have completed".
Select the appropriate figure of speech.
The camel is the ship of the desert.
Answer (Detailed Solution Below)
Literature Question 13 Detailed Solution
Download Solution PDFThe correct answer is option 4), i.e. Metaphor.
Key Points
- A metaphor is a figure of speech which is used to describe a person or an object by directly mentioning another thing or object.
- In the given sentence 'the camel' is described as 'the ship of desert' as it is believed that the camel and the ship have some similar characteristics. So, it is a metaphor.
Important Points
- Pun: A humorous use of words to suggest several meanings of the word or other words which sound alike but have different meanings.
- Personification: When an animal or an inanimate object is given human nature it is called personification.
- Apostrophe: An apostrophe is a figure of speech in which someone is addressed something which is not present.
Directions : Complete each of the sentences given below with the help of the options that follow :
He was _______ by his boss for frequent late coming.
Answer (Detailed Solution Below)
Literature Question 14 Detailed Solution
Download Solution PDFThe correct answer is pulled in.
Key Points
- The correct answer is pulled in, which completes "He was pulled in by his boss for frequent late coming".
- Pulled in: it means to check, restrain etc.
Thus pulled in is the correct answer.
Additional Information
- The phrasal verb pull down means to make somebody less happy, but its real meaning goes as to destroy or take down.
- Pulled up means to check oneself or to stop etc. In different circumstances its used accordingly.
- Pulled on means to hold onto and move (something) toward oneself.
When was Paradise Lost published?
Answer (Detailed Solution Below)
Literature Question 15 Detailed Solution
Download Solution PDFThe correct answer is '1667'.
Key Points
- Paradise Lost is an epic poem in blank verse.
- It is one of the major works of English poet John Milton.
- It was originally issued in 10 books in 1667.
- Later books 7 and 10 were each split into two parts.
- The second edition comprising of 12 books was published in 1674.
Thus, Option 2 is the correct answer.